Sex and the Social Model: Exploring the Role of the Body in the Social Model of Disability

By Maria Grant

 Year 3

Social Policy and Sociology Undergraduate Student

In December 2023, British Vogue published an article by editor and journalist Jennifer McShane, discussing her experiences of sex and sexual wellbeing as a disabled woman, and the joys, challenges, and assumptions that come with it (McShane, 2023). This is the first time a major lifestyle publication has covered the topic of sex and disability, which may be, in part, due to the omission of the body from disability studies and activism in the advent of the social model of disability. This omission is evidenced by the statement from leading social model scholar, Mike Oliver (1996, p. 42), that “disablement has nothing to do with the body.” As the discipline of disability studies and broader social discourse have evolved, however, there have been calls to ‘bring the body back in’ and redevelop a social understanding of disability that includes, but does not medicalise or individualise, the bodies of disabled people.

This paper, therefore, will consider the argument for excluding the body from disability presented by Oliver in the above statement by examining the social model of disability, and criticisms and defences thereof, particularly in relation to the place of the body in disability studies. Relevant literature will then be examined to explore how the body might best be incorporated into the model, before considering potential practical applications through the example of disabled people’s experiences of sexuality and desirability.

Much of the literature and political activism surrounding disability since the late 20th century has been rooted in the social model of disability, which insists that social structures create disability, not individuals’ bodies. The social model was first put forward in definitions provided by the Union of the Physically Impaired Against Segregation in 1976, and further developed by academics in the 1980s, with Oliver (1990) being one of the foremost academics credited with its development (Cameron, 2016). At the heart of the model is the distinction between impairment, taken to mean a chronic physiological or neurological dysfunction (although cognitive impairments/disabilities are scarcely mentioned in early literature – see Owens, 2014), and disability, which is understood as the inability to fully partake in public life because of social structures and organisations that exclude those with impairments (Oliver, 1996). This distinction arose to counter the medical model that took prior dominance, in which disabled people’s bodies were viewed as medical pathologies that must be cured, and people themselves were infantilised and paternalized (Oliver, 1990).

Dissemination of the social model helped to strengthen the disability rights movement in the 1990s and created greater identification across diverse groups of disabled people, as they were now able to unite in the face of common barriers (Cameron, 2016). In turn, then, it contributed to the achievement of rights for disabled people. Thirty years after its creation, Oliver (2013, p. 1025) reflected on how the model and movement “forced the media to change their images of us, transport providers to open up many of their services to us, public buildings to become much more accessible and the legal system changed to make it illegal to discriminate against us.”

The dominant criticism of the social model, however, pertains to the dichotomy drawn between impairment and disability. Anastasiou and Kauffman (2013, p. 449) referred to the model as an “over socialized analysis,” too deeply steeped in social constructionism. They argue that total ignorance of biology and difference would prove detrimental to disabled people, risking the elimination of important specialised services and their own bodily agency and autonomy. They also argue that, in dichotomising corporeal and social experience, the social model ‘leaves’ the body to the medical model, and in so doing continues to facilitate that which it aims to eradicate, namely the continued medicalisation and pathologisation of disabled people and their bodies.

According to Hughes and Patterson (1997), the social model creates these problems by not allowing for a complete and holistic analysis of disabled people’s experiences. They argue that because physical experiences (of pain, for example) and perception are intrinsic to disabled people’s day-to-day lives, a considerable analytical gap is left when they are omitted.

Much of the discourse related to the model, Oliver argues, boils down to differing conceptualisations. The social model, he says, “is not a social theory of disability and it cannot do the work of social theory,” (Oliver, 1996, p. 52), and he denies that the model was ever meant to be “an all-encompassing framework within which everything that happens to disabled people could be understood or explained,” (Oliver, 2013, p. 1024). The social model, he says, is merely one of many tools that can be used to improve the lives of disabled people. He also believes that “the talking to has to stop,” as protracted discussion over what the social model does and does not incorporate detracts from time that could be spent engaged in collective action that would bring about effective change (Oliver, 2013, p. 1026). Christopher Riddle (2020) puts forward a similar argument, stating that discourse over how disability should be conceptualised should not be engaged in until proper equality has been achieved under the social model, and current conversations of the sort are therefore overly prefigurative.

In examining these critiques and defences it must first be acknowledged that, despite Oliver’s claims to the contrary, the place of the social model as the guiding perspective of contemporary social theory on disability is undeniable. This has led to significant advances for the disabled community in the last forty years, but as Levitt (2017) argues, its scope does not need to be and, in fact, has not been, limited to its immediate practical applications or the geo- and socio-political context in which it originated. Moreover, because of the guiding role the model and its definitions have played, the model and its theorists do, in turn, bear some responsibility for the consequences of omitting the body from disability studies. It may, at the time, have been a strategic choice to “leave an overanalysed entity mercifully alone,” (Snyder and Mitchell, 2001, p. 374) but arrogant insistence of the model’s rigidity will not serve the movement going forward. It should also be acknowledged that evolving conceptualisation is not putting “the cart before the horse,” (Riddle, 2020, p. 1510) and that there is no reason for ontological conversation and political action not to take place concurrently.

Hughes and Patterson (1997) put forward two theoretical approaches that they deem best suited to understanding the social place of the body in disability studies. The first is a postmodernist Foucauldian approach, which sees the body as a point of discourse, “an object of knowledge and a target for the exercise of power,” (Hughes and Patterson, 1997, p. 332). This approach can most easily tie in with the social model, for when we consider that many of the barriers the model addresses are tangible, physical barriers (i.e., the built environment), we can observe them as tools deployed by social organisations and structures to exert control over disabled people by way of their bodies.

Hughes and Patterson (1997) see the Foucauldian approach as useful to a certain extent but point out one major flaw: it only views disabled bodies as objects, not subjects of knowledge and discourse, and in so doing “robs the body of agency and renders it biologically barren,” (1997, p. 334). To supplement this gap, therefore, they put forward a phenomenological sociology of the body, applied to disability. This approach understands the body as “an experiencing agent, itself a subject […] and therefore a site of meaning and source of knowledge about the world,” (Merleau-Ponty, 1962, cited in Hughes and Patterson, 1997, p. 334). Phenomenology, in many ways, hearkens back to the philosophy of Aristotle in marking the body as the starting point of all perception, but when applied sociologically, highlights the importance of non-discursive, embodied perception in social interactions. The approach has been utilised very successfully in other fields of social research (see, for example, the work of Vandebroeck, 2016, on the relations between body size and social class) but is of particular importance in disability studies, as impairment and different physiologies not only account for differing means of corporeal perception, but differing, socially influenced, perceptions of the corporeal by others.

Through this combined approach, Huges and Patterson (1997, p. 335-336) truly bridge the gap between impairment and disability by concluding that “disability is experienced in, on and through the body, just as impairment is experienced in terms of the personal and cultural narratives that help to constitute its meaning,” or, more succinctly “disability is embodied, and impairment is social.”

 

The implications of the theories put forward by Hughes and Patterson can be particularly well demonstrated in the arena of disability and sexuality. It is an area with limited yet influential literature (though worth noting that the one ‘Sexuality and Disability’ academic journal is for medical and psychological works, suggesting that the topic is still quite stuck in the medical model).

We can see these ideas and their consequences reflected in Jennifer McShane’s British Vogue article as well. Speaking of her own experiences McShane describes how, because of her disability, it is typically assumed that sexual desire plays no part in her life, to the point that a nurse ‘scoffed away’ the idea of her needing a cervical smear. Such assumptions have been relentlessly reinforced throughout her life, both from the attitudes of friends, family, and potential partners, and a lack of educational or representational media about sex as a disabled person. Now, McShane says, “nothing about [my] pursuit of desire feels natural,” and “it always feels slightly forced, timid, like I shouldn’t really be doing it (pun intended),” (McShane, 2023). In these statements, we can see a clear example of the impact of social norms and structures on a disabled person’s corporeal experiences, and on their perception of their own physiological mechanisms (i.e. sexual desire).

This paper has critically examined the statement put forward by Oliver (1996, p. 42) that “disablement has nothing to do with the body,” by analysing arguments both criticising and defending the social model of disability. It has argued that what is needed is not a separate ‘social model of impairment,’ as Oliver (1996) alluded to, but a re-incorporation of the body into disability studies and the social model that is grounded in suitable, pre-existing, and already clearly applicable social theory. It then outlined some of the theories that are best fit for conducting this incorporation, and used the example of disability and sexuality to consider how they can be practically applied in contemporary social discourse.

To conclude, it must be said that we have certainly not transcended the need for the social model of disability, as the inequalities and injustices it seeks to address have by no means been eradicated. However, the conversations around disability are advancing regardless and it may, therefore, be time to allow for a more nuanced, embodied iteration of the model that would, in turn, provide for increasingly comprehensive social studies on a wider scale.

Anastasiou, D., Kauffman, J.M., (2013), ‘The Social Model of Disability: Dichotomy between Impairment and Disability,’ The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for Bioethics and Philosophy of Medicine, 38(4), pp. 441- 459.

Attwood, F., (2011) ‘Sex and the Media,’ in Ross, K.(ed.), The Handbook of Gender, Sex, and Media, Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons, Incorporated, pp. 457-469

Cameron, C., (2016), ‘The Social Model,’ in Cameron, C. (ed.), Disability Studies: A Student’s Guide, London: SAGE Publications Ltd., pp. 137-140.

Goodley, D., (2013), ‘Dis/entangling Critical Disability Studies,’ in Disability & Society, 28(5), pp. 631-644.

Hughes, B., Patterson, K., (1997), ‘The Social Model of Disability and the Disappearing Body: Towards a Sociology of Impairment,’ Disability & Society, 12(3), pp. 325-340.

Levitt, J.M., (2017), ‘Exploring How the Social Model of Disability Can Be Re-invigorated: In Response to Mike Oliver,’ in Disability & Society, 32(4), pp. 589-594.

Naples, N.A., Mauldin, L., Dillaway, H., (2019), ‘Gender, Disability, and Intersectionality,’ in Gender & Society, 33(1), pp. 5-18.

Oliver, M., (1990), The Politics of Disablement, 1st edn., London: Macmillan Press.

Oliver, M., (1996), ‘Defining Impairment and Disability: Issues at Stake,’ in Barnes, C., Mercer, G., (eds), Exploring the Divide: Illness and Disability, Leeds: The Disability Press, pp. 39-54.

Oliver, M., (2013) ‘The Social Model of Disability: Thirty Years On,’ in Disability & Society, 28(7), pp. 1024–1026.

Owens, J., (2014), ‘Exploring the Critiques of the Social Model of Disability: The Transformative Possibility of Arendt’s Notion of Power,’ in Sociology of Health and Illness, 37(3), pp. 385-403.

Pepper, P., (2016), ‘Treating Disabled People as Asexual is Exasperating and Offensive,’ The Guardian, June 8. Available at: https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2016/jun/08/disabled-people-asexual-sex-lives-you-before-me-sexuality (Accessed 20 February 2024)

Riddle, C.A., (2020) ‘Why We Do Not Need a ‘Stronger’ Social Model of Disability,’ in Disability & Society, 35(9), pp. 1509-1513.

Shildrick, M., (2005), ‘The Disabled Body, Genealogy and Undecidability,’ in Cultural Studies, 19(6), pp. 755-770.

Shildrick, M., (2009), Dangerous Discourses of Disability, Subjectivity and Sexuality, 1st edn., London: Palgrave Macmillan.

Shildrick, M., (2016), ‘Sexuality.’ in Cameron, C. (ed.), Disability Studies: A Student’s Guide, London: SAGE Publications Ltd., pp. 135-136.

Snyder, S.L., Mitchell, D.T., (2001) ‘Re-engaging the Body: Disability Studies and the Resistance to Embodiment,’ in Public Culture, 13(3), pp. 367-389. Vandebroeck, D., (2016), Distinctions in the Flesh: Social Class and the Embodiment of Inequality, 1st ed., London: Routledge